Dual Process Theory Opposes Decision Theory?
Do any of the findings that support the dual-process theory of instrumental action enable us to construct a good objection to decision theory as an elucidation of subjective probabilities and preferences?
Notes
Background
The dual-process theory of instrumental action was introduced in
Goal-Directed and Habitual Processes.
We considered decision theory as an
elucidation of subjective probabilities and preferences
in What Are Preferences?.
Argument
The following claims cannot all be true:
-
Instrumental actions maximise agents’ expected utilities.
-
Decision theory provides an ‘elucidation of the notions of subjective probability and subjective desirability or utility’ (Jeffrey, 1983, p. xi).
-
The notions elucidated are those of belief and desire, which also feature in the model of goal-directed processes.
-
Some instrumental actions are dominated by habitual processes (see Goal-Directed and Habitual: Some Evidence).
-
Habitual and goal-directed processes can pull in opposing directions (see The Minor Puzzle about Habitual Action).
What think that these are jointly inconsistent?
Because their truth would indicate that we have no grounds to expect agents to
act in accordance with the axioms required to make (1) true.
The joint inconsistency of these claims is significant:
it suggests that we cannot use decision theory as an anchor for thinking about notions of belief and desire.
But perhaps there is a way to avoid this conclusion?
Are the claims actually inconsistent?
Or is there some way to use
decision theory as an anchor for thinking about notions of belief and desire
despite the inconsistency of the above claims?
Ask a Question
Your question will normally be answered in the question
session of the next lecture.
More information about asking questions.
Glossary
anchor :
A theory, fact or other thing that is used by a group of researchers to ensure
that they have a shared understanding of a phenomenon.
An anchor is needed when it is unclear whether different researchers are offering
incompatible claims about a single phenomenon or compatible claims about distinct phenomena.
For example, we might take decision theory
to anchor a shared understanding of belief and desire.
decision theory :
I use ‘decision theory’ for the theory elaborated by Jeffrey (1983). Variants are variously called ‘expected utility theory’ (Hargreaves-Heap & Varoufakis, 2004), ‘revealed preference theory’ (Sen, 1973) and ‘the theory of rational choice’ (Sugden, 1991). As the differences between variants are not important for our purposes, the term can be used for any of core formal parts of the standard approaches based on Ramsey (1931) and Savage (1972).
dual-process theory of instrumental action :
Instrumental action ‘is controlled by two dissociable processes: a
goal-directed and an habitual process’ (Dickinson, 2016, p. 177).
(See instrumental action.)
goal-directed process :
A process which involves ‘a
representation of the causal relationship between the action and outcome
and a representation of the current incentive value, or utility, of the
outcome’ and which influences an action ‘in a way that rationalizes
the action as instrumental for attaining the goal’ (Dickinson, 2016, p. 177).
habitual process :
A process underpinning some instrumental actions which obeys
Thorndyke’s Law of Effect:
‘The presentation of an effective [=rewarding] outcome following an action [...] reinforces
a connection between the stimuli present when the action is performed and the action itself
so that subsequent presentations of these stimuli elicit the [...] action as a response’
(Dickinson, 1994, p. 48).
(Interesting complication which you can safely ignore: there is probably much more to say about
under what conditions the stimulus–action connection is strengthened; e.g. Thrailkill, Trask, Vidal, Alcalá, & Bouton, 2018.)
References
Chater, N. (2018).
The Mind is Flat: The Illusion of Mental Depth and The Improvised Mind. Penguin UK.
Davidson, D. (1987). Problems in the explanation of action. In P. Pettit, R. Sylvan, & J. Norman (Eds.),
Metaphysics and morality: Essays in honour of j. J. C. smart (pp. 35–49). Oxford: Blackwell.
Dickinson, A. (1994). Instrumental conditioning. In N. Mackintosh (Ed.),
Animal learning and cognition. London: Academic Press.
Dickinson, A. (2016). Instrumental conditioning revisited: Updating dual-process theory. In J. B. Trobalon & V. D. Chamizo (Eds.),
Associative learning and cognition (Vol. 51, pp. 177–195). Edicions Universitat Barcelona.
Hargreaves-Heap, S., & Varoufakis, Y. (2004).
Game theory: A critical introduction. London: Routledge. Retrieved from
http://webcat.warwick.ac.uk/record=b2587142~S1
Jeffrey, R. C. (1983).
The logic of decision, second edition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Ramsey, F. (1931). Truth and probability. In R. Braithwaite (Ed.),
The foundations of mathematics and other logical essays. London: Routledge.
Savage, L. J. (1972).
The foundations of statistics (2nd rev. ed). New York: Dover Publications.
Sen, A. (1973). Behaviour and the Concept of Preference.
Economica,
40(159), 241–259.
https://doi.org/10.2307/2552796
Sugden, R. (1991). Rational Choice: A Survey of Contributions from Economics and Philosophy.
The Economic Journal,
101(407), 751–785.
https://doi.org/10.2307/2233854
Thrailkill, E. A., Trask, S., Vidal, P., Alcalá, J. A., & Bouton, M. E. (2018). Stimulus control of actions and habits: A role for reinforcer predictability and attention in the development of habitual behavior.
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Learning and Cognition,
44, 370–384.
https://doi.org/10.1037/xan0000188
Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty.
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty,
5(4), 297–323.
https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00122574
Endnotes